Miranda Yaver, PhD
  • About
  • CV
  • Research
  • Teaching
  • Blog
  • Comedy
  • Other Writing
  • Other
  • Contact

SUPREME COURT STRIKES DOWN TEXAS ABORTION CONSTRAINTS IN WHOLE WOMAN'S HEALTH

6/30/2016

0 Comments

 
In Planned Parenthood v. Casey (1992), the Supreme Court evaluated in light of Roe v. Wade (1973) the constitutionality of a Pennsylvania law mandating a 24-waiting period prior to obtaining abortions, and in so doing established a new standard according to which the Court determined whether the purpose of the given restriction was to impose an "undue burden" on the woman seeking the abortion. An undue burden was construed as a "substantial obstacle in the path of a woman seeking an abortion before the fetus attains viability." This landmark holding on abortion policy paved the way toward state innovation in abortion policy to test the reach of this "undue burden" provision that the Court's 5-4 majority laid out. 

In the years since, states have answered the call. For example, 43 states prohibit abortions after a specified point of the pregnancy, typically fetus viability; 19 states prohibit late-term ("partial birth") abortions; 32 states and the District of Columbia prohibit the use of state funds except where federal funds are available (to protect the life of the woman or in the case of rape or incest); 17 states mandate that women receive counseling prior to obtaining an abortion; 27 states mandate that women wait a specified amount of time between receiving counseling and receiving the abortion (typically 24 hours but as many as 72); and 38 states require some parental involvement in obtaining an abortion for a minor, with 25 of those states requiring parental consent and 13 states requiring notification but not consent of the parent.

Whole Woman's Health v. Hellerstedt (2016), decided in a surprise 5-3 decision with Justice Kennedy (also in the majority in Planned Parenthood v. Casey) joining the liberal coalition,  centered on the Texas State Legislature's HB 2, passed in 2013 and signed into law by then-Governor Rick Perry. HB 2 out a number of provisions pertaining to abortions under the guise of protecting the health of the women in question but with the ultimate effect of precluding providers from meeting standards necessary to lawfully provide abortion access to those in need. Among those provisions were that physicians performing abortions have admitting privileges at a hospital within 30 miles of where the abortion was being performed, and that the abortion facility meet the requirements of ambulatory surgical centers despite the fact that abortions are highly safe outpatient procedures (indeed, evaluating the risks of childbirth versus abortions, compared with a mortality rate of 8.8 deaths per 100,000 live births, there is a mortality rate of 0.6 deaths per 100,000 abortions). While nominally still allowing abortion access, the legislation was deemed to have the effect of all but eliminating abortion facilities in the State of Texas. 

To impose marked restraints on abortion access is not unheard of. The State of Missouri has only 1 abortion provider in the entire state, and 89% of counties in the United States have no abortion provider. States are not always overt in their means of excluding abortion access, rather imposing requirements in the name of "safety," with the notion that satisfying the requirements of being a surgical suite will be positively correlated with the health outcomes of the abortions performed there. (Remember, even absent this requirement in most states, the mortality rate is still extraordinarily low). While meeting high standards of medical care is all well and good, the types of regulations that the legislation targets involve such issues as the width of corridors and the size of procedure rooms, neither criteria of which are demonstrably associated with better patient outcomes. (After all, when in the first ten weeks of pregnancy, it can be carried out without any procedure but rather with the so-called "abortion pill," or Mifepristone (RU 486)).The marked implications of such legislation has garnered it the title "clinic shutdown" law, and in the aftermath of the legislation's passage, while Texas previously had approximately forty abortion clinics, approximately half had closed due to the requirement of admitting privileges, and it was estimated that only eight or nine would remain if enforcing provisions requiring that the clinics meet the requirements of surgical centers. 

In his majority opinion, Justice Breyer noted the absence of scientific evidence for the necessity of HB 2, writing that "there was no significant health-related problem that the new law helped to cure." The majority cites a number of studies brought to the attention of the Court, noting that among first trimester abortion complications, the highest rate of major complications was less than 0.25%, and that even in the rarer second trimester abortion, the rate of major complication was still less than 0.5%, and that complication only required hospital admission 0.23% of the time and not necessarily on the day of the abortion (making admitting privileges far from a necessity, particularly given that patients will not be turned away from an emergency room). Thus, the majority notes, "We have found nothing in Texas’ record evidence that shows that, compared to prior law (which required a 'working arrangement' with a doctor with admitting privileges), the new law advanced Texas’ legitimate interest in protecting women’s health. We add that, when directly asked at oral argument whether Texas knew of a single instance in which the new requirement would have helped even one woman obtain better treatment, Texas admitted that there was no evidence in the record of such a case."

While not providing evidence in support of the health advantages of this different standard of care, the Court notes that the admitting privileges requirement appeared to have had a marked impact on abortion facility closures, with the number of women of reproductive age living 150 miles or farther from an abortion provider going from 86,000 to 400,000, and the additional problems of longer waiting times, fewer doctors, and increased crowding. While increasing the driving distance is not alone enough to support a claim of undue burden, the Court said, the increases constitute an "additional burden" that combine with the abortion clinic closures and the virtually absent proven health benefit to support the District Court's finding that HB 2 constituted an "undue burden" in violation of Casey.

A number of states have so-called TRAP (targeted regulation of abortion providers) laws, which the Court's recent holding will implicate. Not unlike Casey, while affirming the right to abortion, the Court here still did not hold that any restriction on abortion access constitutes an undue burden. Indeed, effecting a change that would have the result of some clinic closures might still pass constitutional muster. But the intent and effect of the legislation here, given the absence of scientific support and the clearly marked policy effects, were both to restrict if not altogether preclude abortion access to an extent within the realm of the "undue burden" that Casey sought to avoid in negotiating reproductive freedom at the national level and the right of states to forge their own paths (within bounds). What remains to be seen is the extent to which Texas abortion facilities will reopen in the aftermath of the decision, and the trajectory of policy in the other states that had enacted similar legislation (for example, Arizona, on which I wrote previously). 

The Court appealed to states' legitimate interest in protecting women's health, with police powers -- typically, the protection of health, safety, and welfare -- typically falling within states' regulatory prerogatives under the Tenth Amendment. What is, of course, at odds in the abortion debate is what precisely constitutes protection of health, safety, and welfare. As Breyer finds, "The surgical-center requirement also provides few, if any, health benefits for women, poses a substantial obstacle to women seeking abortions, and constitutes an 'undue burden' on their constitutional right to do so... Record evidence shows that the new provision imposes a number of additional requirements that are generally unnecessary in the abortion clinic context." The Court rightly emphasized the health benefits, or lack thereof, provided by HB 2 (and by extension, other TRAP laws imposed by states) relative to other policies according to which women may obtain abortions. But an important additional dimension of states' protection of women's (indeed, citizens') health and safety is that in the absence of abortion access. 

By making abortion less accessible (reminder: these are laws on the ability to provide abortions and thus do not create exceptions for rape or incest), women are more likely to obtain abortions later in their pregnancy, and while abortions are very safe early in the pregnancy (when the vast majority of abortions are performed), the risks do go up when performed later (though as the statistics cited above indicate, the risks are still low). If unable to obtain a legal abortion, one may be more likely to seek an illegal, unregulated abortion, thus subjecting oneself to a host of potential harms to which one is not exposed when in regulated medical care. Indeed, cracking down on legalized abortion has been argued by some to have more impact on the safety than the incidence of abortion. And if one is unable to provide adequate care to a child but is unable to terminate the pregnancy, we are not only sentencing women to motherhood but are faced with a further question of whose life we really are protecting. If we are only protecting life before birth, we might need to reevaluate what we're fighting for. 

The Supreme Court's decision in Whole Woman's Health made important progress toward cracking down on overly restrictive state legislation and better defining what falls within the realm of "undue burden" on women's reproductive choice. By implication, the similar laws in effect in dozens of other states will likely be determined to be unconstitutional, though time will tell the speed with which we see policy changes go into effect.
0 Comments

NEEDING TO KNOW WHERE TO LOOK FOR PRESCRIPTION DRUG SAVINGS

6/18/2016

0 Comments

 
​I don’t want to need it.
 
That is a thought that has been all too familiar to me when I venture on the patient side of health care, an industry that I study as a scholar as well with the distance of one investigating a foreign land in which they do not intend to become entrenched.
 
It is a thought that has been all too familiar as I see added to my daily regimen new medications, some of which I trust, others of which I am skeptical after reading reports on the industries that brought them to the market. I am, after all, familiar with the pharmaceutical industry and, while well aware that many have been able to manage well their conditions thanks to their products, am also not without cynicism as to their profit-based motivations.
 
“I don’t want to need it,” is not a mature response to a debacle. It does not remedy the need, nor does it even truly acknowledge the need. It merely resents the medical treatment, the need of which remains in doubt. What it does not ignore is the problem, and the prescription for its solution, whether that prescription is proper or not.
 
I have been on countless medications over the last five years. What has surprised me more than the prescriptions for various medications – some of which I had never heard of previously, and others of which I had heard of through direct-to-consumer ads, which I dislike on principle – is the business aspect of these pharmaceutical companies with which I have been confronted in a way that I have seen discussed precious little: copay savings cards.
 
I was pleased at first. My otherwise $300 sleeping medication got promptly knocked down to $30, which almost made me forget that this particular doctor seemed to engage quite frequently with representatives from the pharmaceutical company pushing the drug. Almost, but not quite.
 
A couple of months later, a new medication got added to the mix to address a chronic parathyroid disorder. When seeing the price of $80 show up (post-insurance) on the pharmacy website made me wince, I did some research on the company website and other sources to weigh the (literal) costs and benefits of the medication. Lo and behold, the distributor Amgen provided a prescription savings card that knocked the price from $80 to $5. For $5, I’ll take my chances with the medication and see if it works for me.
 
Some research confirmed that these savings cards are not totally anomalous, and I have encountered them – sometimes in advance of filling prescriptions, and alas sometimes after the fact – with respect to other medications prescribed to me. And while it is normatively desirable to curb the rising costs of prescription drugs, what is striking about these savings cards is the limited information as to their very existence. My doctors did not point me in this direction. Nor did the pharmacist at Walgreens. I don’t expect that their failure to do so was in any way nefarious – they get no benefit from my paying $5 versus $80 per month – but it is unfortunate that their use depends on the patient being fastidious in their research prior to filling a new prescription.
 
Such an assumption may not be met given many individuals’ trust in, and deference toward doctors’ decisionmaking, with 70% of  Gallup survey respondents confident in the accuracy of their doctor’s medical advice and only 29% viewing it necessary to do their own research (though some research does support a decline in the public’s trust in physicians). Moreover, within this field in which there is ample information asymmetry – with the general public typically not as familiar (or for that matter, capable of becoming so) with the specifics of the medical decisionmaking (see, e.g., Arrow 1963) and potentially unlikely to research the cost-benefit analysis of prescription drugs and other medical treatments. The (even more) cynical part of me is left wondering whether prescription drug companies price their drugs higher than necessary to account for the use of such savings cards, akin to accounting for future "sales" in regular product pricing.
 
There is the additional concern that those who are engaging in that research are not the ones most in need of prescription savings. If – as I strongly suspect – those who do conduct their own research on medical treatments are those who are more highly educated and, relatedly, higher on the income ladder, then benefits are not being distributed appropriately. Sure, people of all income levels enjoy their tax breaks. But those who need the money are not those of higher socioeconomic status, but rather those living paycheck to paycheck and for whom the price of prescription drugs impacts adherence to medication regimens.  
 
Indeed, 20-30% of medication prescriptions are never filled, and 50% of medication prescriptions are not continued as prescribed, with medication adherence dropping after the first six months of following a given regimen. I am the first to confess that I contribute toward these numbers, partly out of frustration of several-times-a-day reminders of a need that I resent, and often out of financial concerns that trump medical concerns.
 
To be clear, these figures are not all attributable to prescription drug costs. Some may be attributable to skepticism, denial about the need for a given treatment, or a frustration with particular side effects that accompany the given drug. But it is difficult to imagine that prescription drug costs are a negligible contributor toward these numbers, which is particularly distressing given that non-adherence carries an economic cost of an estimated $100 to 249 billion annually as of 2009, while improved self-management of chronic diseases is estimated as having a 1:10 cost to savings ratio. It can literally pay to better incentivize adherence (at least setting aside the many questions as to whether we are being systematically over-treated in the American healthcare system).
 
That drug manufacturers provide greater savings to patients is doubtless advantageous in making it more feasible to treat illnesses without causing as much financial burden. As someone at the relatively unusual intersection of high education and relatively low income (lucky me), I am also, I suspect, at the relatively unusual intersection of conducting extensive medical research and benefiting immensely from any financial savings that come my way as a result. But were I less skeptical about the industry with which I interact all-too-much, I would not know that I could reap this reward.
 
It is unclear whether it is nefariously intentional on the part of prescription drug manufacturers that such savings be more in theory than in practice, relying on unrealistic expectations of consumers to do their own research on the medical and financial costs and benefits that they can expect, or whether this is simply a problem of information dissemination (or rather, lack thereof). To be sure, drug manufacturers stand to gain through their use relative to the financial losses incurred from consumers’ shifts to generic drugs instead. But physicians whose patients’ progress is monitored, and as the numbers above suggest, the American economy as a whole, all stand to gain as well. Increasing physician awareness of, and communication about, copay savings for prescription drugs will go a long way toward reducing reliance on consumers’ own savviness to do so, and in turn enhancing adherence to treatments prescribed. 
0 Comments

SUPREME COURT RULES UNANIMOUSLy on FALSE CLAIMS ACT

6/16/2016

0 Comments

 
In its unanimous opinion delivered on June 16, 2016, the Supreme Court decided the case of Universal Health Services v. United States ex rel. Escobar regarding the False Claims Act. The opinion was authored by Justice Clarence Thomas, and held that companies can be subject to False Claims Act liability and implied certification claims, under two conditions: 1) when the claim does not only request payment but also "makes specific recommendations about the goods or services provided"; and 2) the defendant's failure to disclose noncompliance with requirements must make its representations "misleading half-truths."   

The case arose in the aftermath of the death of a Medicaid beneficiary being treated by Arbour Counseling Services, a behavioral health center operated by Universal Health Services and in which many of the staff were lacking in proper certification and supervision (indeed, the treating psychologist who identified herself as having a PhD failed to disclose that it was received from an unaccredited Internet college at that the State of Massachusetts had denied her application to be licensed as a psychologist; further, the medication was prescribed by one who lacked the authority to do so absent supervision). The clinic misrepresented the staff credentials, submitted numerous claims for Medicaid treatment, and the Medicaid program promptly paid those claims to Arbour, which has been subject to a number of investigations pertaining to such issues as billing practices, poor care, and inadequate staffing: "At Arbour-HRI two years ago, public health officials found the hospital failed to provide active treatment to some patients, whose diagnoses included bipolar disorder and paranoid schizophrenia. Instead of attending group therapy, inspectors said, patients spent many hours sleeping or wandering the hallways — an allegation the company disputed."

The First Circuit Court of Appeals held that implied in claims submissions is compliance with conditions for payments. To determine whether a claim was indeed fraudulent, one must ascertain "whether the defendant, in submitting a claim for reimbursement, knowingly misrepresented compliance with a material precondition for payment" (780 F.3d 512 (2015)). The Court granted cert to resolve the lower courts' disputes as to the scope of implied false certification theory of liability.

The Supreme Court addressed the question of what precisely it means to submit false claims under the False Claims Act (FCA), given that the services in this case technically were provided (albeit from those without proper qualification or transparency). The Supreme Court held that the failure to reveal this information regarding treatment providers was actionable under the FCA. Prior to this ruling, while implied certification has been the subject of a number of suits brought against providers, the federal courts have been divided as to the proper resolution of the legal challenges.  The recent Supreme Court decision has been seen as striking a balance between combating health care fraud claims and protecting against what some might construe as "frivolous lawsuits" over the FCA. Indeed, the Court clarifies that "the False Claims Act is not a means of imposing treble damages and other penalties for insignificant regulatory or contractual violations" and the Court did not address the issues of medical malpractice of which Arbour and other Universal Health Services-owned hospitals have been accused. While a number of health providers may newly be concerned regarding the potential FCA-related consequences of non-adherence to Medicare and Medicaid requirements, the Court's emphasis on significant legal and regulatory contractual obligations appears (perhaps consistent with its being unanimous in a time of marked polarization in both the legislative and judicial branches) a very reasonable approach to balancing ensuring effective enforcement while not leading to excessive litigation.  
0 Comments

ON THE SEEMINGLY LOST ART OF WRITING

6/6/2016

0 Comments

 
​Reflecting in “Ode, Intimations of Immortality” on the diminished delights that he experienced relative to his youth, William Wordsworth wrote, “The rainbow comes and goes/ And lovely is the rose;/ The moon doth with delight/ Look round her when the heavens are bare;/ Waters on a starry night/ Are beautiful and fair;/ The sunshine is a glorious birth;/ But yet I know, where’er I go/ That there hath pass’d away a glory from the earth.”
 
At the risk of sounding like an overly curmudgeonly individual longing for the “good old days” – I know that I am too young to pull off such a rant in earnest (an am hardly one to contribute toward such a debate in the context of such issues as civility and profanity) – I can’t help but find myself despondent over the current state of affairs where writing is concerned. This feeling has been rendered all the more acute as in my health policy research I bask in the prose of Kalanithi’s When Breath Becomes Air and Gawande’s Being Mortal, both in themselves poignant reflections on what makes life meaningful, but also standing out in the language with which these physicians and writers conveyed these messages. Such talent for prose is not as common as one might hope among those in the sciences (or even the social sciences, for that matter) given the emphasis on statistical significance levels, science, and technical writing to the exclusion of eloquent prose. Yet through this powerful mode of communication, they connect with their readers about this important subject matter and render it all too easy to sigh wistfully and wonder why this is seemingly so rare.  
 
When I was a young child, I admittedly was quite advanced where reading was concerned. In elementary and middle school, I was reading Pride and Prejudice, Emma, Jane Eyre, Little Women, Gone with the Wind, the list goes on. Elizabeth Bennett and Jo March were the kindred spirits with whom I spent my summer afternoons. When I was a little older, it was Salinger, Hemingway, Faulkner, Eliot, Borges, Sartre, Kafka, Fitzgerald, Marquez, Baudelaire, and so many more.
 
A former professor of mine from graduate school advised that if given the choice between being a reader and being a writer, one should be a writer. Setting aside the joy that one can get from reading great writing (admittedly, this was professional and not personal advice toward developing a scholarly career), it is good advice, though with the caveat that reading great writing can inspire one to do the same. Indeed, I find that the greatest antidote to writers’ block is to read writing that inspires me, often in the tone that I most want to emulate. When I seek inspiration to write fiction, I read Faulkner. When I am writing more humorous fiction or creative nonfiction, I read Salinger, or perhaps on a more contemporary note, Carrie Fisher. When I need discipline in academic writing, there is no greater discipliner than Hemingway, whose prose took longer to grow on me than did the writing of Fitzgerald, but who over time has held up better as far more modern.   
 
My favorite poet, T.S. Eliot, said famously, “Immature writers imitate. Mature writers steal.” But stealing must be from a good source. Whether intentionally or not, we are often influenced by that which we read. It is unclear to me the most prominent culprit or combination of culprits: whether it is that schools have stopped assigning to students as many of the great writers whom we studied previously (I do not believe that this is the case), whether the average quality of writing in previous generations was not lower than the present but that which has survived is simply the upper tail of the distribution and thus is an unrepresentative sample against which we judge the present (potentially true, though some evidence supports a decline in quality over the course of the last few years and an entire Tumblr page is dedicated to the tortured writing submitted to teachers along with the students' mangled history accounts (e.g., an apparent belief that Martin Luther freed the slaves with his "I Have a Dream" speech)), whether the 24/7 nature of media and entertainment has reduced the quality of what people read outside of the classroom, whether it is that we have stopped teaching people how to write well in school, or whether the use of social media has induced an excessive casualness to writing that has reduced its overall quality. It is clear that people read fewer books now than in years previous, with an all-time high of 23% of Americans not having read a book in the last year in 2014, compared with just 8% in 1978 (though this trend is not unique to Americans, as a fifth of adults in the UK reportedly do not know who wrote "Hamlet", while a third did not know who wrote Great Expectations). People become all-too-accustomed to finding shortcuts to communicating ideas – u instead of you, thx instead of thanks, r instead of are, and the like – and forget how to take the traditional let alone the scenic routes of written communication.    
 
To be sure, as a former New Yorker (and still, a New Yorker at heart even when walking the streets of Saint Louis), I succumb to the walking equivalent of the modal American’s attitude toward writing. I speed walk even if I am not in a hurry. I rush those in front of me regardless of whether I have two minutes or two hours to arrive at my intended destination. I take shortcuts unless the walk is for the purpose of exercise (which I usually do at the gym, where I find my exercise regimen more efficient). I know that within this domain, just as others view writing through the domain of the internet, I value efficiency over the quality of experience (though to be sure I still enjoy a more leisurely jog through Riverside Park, the Hudson River and the land of my favorite musician off to the right and trees and relatively sparse populations of tourists to my left as my feet beat against the pavement for a few miles.
 
In an era of expecting instant rewards, not to mention experiencing constant distractions with technology, expecting one to curl up with Anna Karenina (let alone finish it) has become a lot to ask of an individual. I am by no means advocating any reduction in technology for the sake of living a la Thoreau for a time. Take away my iPhone, and my anxiety goes from a level 3 to a level 8 instantly from that single treatment effect. We read synopses instead of the real thing. We cut to the chase. We compress messages to the virtual universe into text messages or 140 (often grammatically incorrect) characters, despite the fact that at least 30% of adult Twitter users have a college degree or higher (as do 74% of Facebook users). “Text speak” has become so common that a list of hundreds of such expressions has been accumulated, including such phrases as 2G2BT (“too good to be true”), 4e (“forever”), gn8 (“goodnight”), w8 (“wait), and the like. It has apparently become a norm well beyond Tigger’s “TTFN – ta ta for now”). And yet there is such simplicity in the pleasure of curling up with a blanket and a book (and in my case, a cat) and losing oneself in the Hemingway’s Paris or Leopold Bloom’s interior monologue, a simplicity that today seems to be all too lost. What’s more, writing – or more specifically, good writing – can do so much good in the way of raising human consciousness to important issues as a number of prominent physicians have done on issues of health, medicine, and bioethics.
 
Harold Bloom’s unapologetic advocacy in favor of the “great books” is something to which I am sympathetic in an era of greater valuing of those degrees that are lucrative or more likely to pave the way toward lucrative professions, not to mention a depressing decline if not death of quality journalism. (As someone whose second major very nearly was Classics with a minor in English Literature, I was not at the age of twenty a shining example of following the path of practicality). It is not simply because of my desire for my students to get my references, though that of course would be nice (though to their credit, they consistently do get my Sorkin references). It is not simply because I appreciate reading their extra rhetorical flourish, though to be sure I do. And I do not have evidence to support that the decline in students’ and others’ writing is a reflection on not being exposed to the “right” people to emulate or if it is merely a reflection on our declining premium that we place on writing (while we do need to invest in better education, my strong suspicion is that it is the latter scenario, as the works of Austen and Hemingway will forever be in print and available for public consumption). There must also be a will to adapt, or in this case more aptly, to revert. It is out of my optimism, my hope that in becoming reacquainted with the greats (and recognizing them as such), we might renew our attention to the seemingly lost art of what it means to be both great writers (whether fiction or nonfiction), and more broadly great communicators.
0 Comments

END OF LIFE CARE, AND WHEN BREATH BECOMES AIR

6/2/2016

0 Comments

 
En route to Cornell University for a conference today, I read a book that had only recently come on my radar, admittedly very belatedly given my long and ever-growing interest in public health and medicine.
 
Within the pages of When Breath Becomes Air, one finds the at once inspiring and heart-wrenching account of a neurosurgeon, Paul Kalanithi, who succumbed to stage four cancer early in his career, and who brilliantly put pen to paper to reflect on medical ethics, on the humanity of medicine that can at times get lost in aggressive treatment, and on what it means to build a meaningful life. Such work speaks to that of Atul Gawande, whose Being Mortal likewise reflects on the role of modern medicine in shaping not only survival, but also the quality of life with which patients ultimately are left. Purpose, after all, is not universal, and indeed it is something with which Kalanithi grapples throughout his work of dually serving as physician and patient – whether to be a surgeon, a teacher, a writer, a husband, a father. Whether to be a writer for one year or a surgeon for five. With possibilities virtually limits where his intellectual capacity was concerned, within the confines of his illness, the choice was his, and as he notes, that feeling of purpose is itself fluid given the trajectory of his disease and the options before him.   
 
Medicine is about healing, but it is multidimensional in working toward that end. Medical interventions almost invariably are accompanied by potential benefits as well as potential harms, thus leaving the patient to make some degree of cost-benefit calculus with respect to the decision whether to pursue treatment. Interventions can sometimes make us worse even en route to making us better. It can also, at times, be at odds with personal preferences for valuing quality of life versus longevity, a trade-off that is at the heart of deciding for oneself what it means for a life to be meaningful.
 
Indeed, for all the emphasis on saving human life, in some cases amid the needless to say important statistics and randomized controlled trials and the like, the human aspect of medicine is not always front and center amid discussions of longevity. And yet, buying one an additional five years is not always the goal if those years involve the notoriously difficult chemotherapy. Kalanithi writes:
 
“Amid the tragedies and failures, I feared I was losing sight of the singular importance of human relationships, not between patients and their families but between doctor and patient. Technical excellence was not enough. As a resident, my highest ideal was not saving lives – everyone dies eventually – but guiding a patient or family to an understanding of death or illness… For amid that unique suffering invoked by severe brain damage, the suffering often felt more by families than by patients, it is not merely the physicians who do not see the full significance. The families who gather around their beloved – their beloved whose sheared heads contain battered brains – do not usually recognize the full significance, either. They see the past, the accumulation of memories, the freshly felt love, all represented by the body before them. I see the possible futures, the breathing machines connected through a surgical opening in the neck, the pasty liquid dripping in through a hole in the belly, the possible long, painful, and only partial recovery – or, sometimes more likely, no return at all of the person they remember. In these moments, I acted not, as I most often did, as death’s enemy, but as its ambassador. I had to help those families understand that the person they knew – the full, vital independent human – now lived only in the past and that I needed their input to understand what sort of future he or she would want: an easy death or to be strung between bags of fluid going in, others coming out, to persist despite being unable to struggle. Had I been more religious in my youth, I might have become a pastor, for it was the pastoral role I’d sought” (87-88).
 
The eloquence with which he writes on this subject is remarkable, though the substance is in some ways intuitive despite being an uncommon perspective to hear from within medicine.
 
While public trust in doctors has historically been high, the International Social Survey Programme (ISSP) survey of public trust in American physicians from 1966 to 2014 reflected a decline from 73% to 34% expressing great confidence in the U.S. medical profession, despite there not being a similar decline in trust in physicians’ integrity or honesty and ethical standards. Interestingly, a growing minority of Americans argue that doctors ought to do everything possible to keep their patients alive, though arguably it should remain on the patient’s terms. Perhaps surprisingly, the United States is tied for 24th place in ranking of the proportion of adults viewing doctors in their country as being able to be trusted. This is particularly problematic because medicine is a field in which there is extensive asymmetric information. In simpler tasks, one can educate oneself, become expert, fact check. Medicine requires rigorous training in medical school, residency, and fellowship, and thus there is a greater differential between patient and expert (potentially even, as Kalanithi writes, as a patient who is also a physician). This is all the more crucial a disparity when considering that people enter this system often at their most vulnerable (and under those vulnerable conditions, there can be adverse consequences of bad news being delivered poorly to patients).
 
This vulnerability makes all the more important the preservation of the human side of medicine, even if it requires a broadening of the understanding of what it might in fact mean to “do no harm.” The notion of being able to intervene with a medical “fix” is tempting, even if only a temporary fix as opposed to no fix at all, but as Gawande notes, having the different kind of conversation – one involving more listening than talking, considering of the broader set of options and priorities – is difficult, and is it a conversation for which many physicians are ill-prepared, but it is also essential to good patient care (certainly with respect to end-of-life care). There is perhaps no more painful example than that of cognitive deterioration due to such conditions as Alzheimer’s or dementia, with an intact physical body of an individual who is no longer recognizable.
 
There are several types of courage to which Kalanithi’s work speaks directly. The courage of a patient, who must by definition be patient in enduring tests, procedures, probabilistic outcomes rather than a definitive future, pain, and other unpleasantness that she can choose to endure, to rage against the dying of the light, or to, as in Longfellow’s “Thanatopsis,” wrap the drapery of his couch about him and lie down to pleasant dreams. There is the courage of the doctor in fighting in the face of medical uncertainty and uphill battles, but also the courage to know when to allow the patient to be in the driver’s seat, to find the optimal balance between professional command and humility. And the courage as human beings – patients, doctors, teachers, children, parents – to persist in the face of adversity as we so often do throughout our lives (whether with hurdles great or small), and to know at what point to accept the equally brave task of moving toward the next stage of life, or rather its completion. We are taught to fight, to win, to “beat it,” and that to do otherwise is to admit defeat. This is not a defense of preemptive defeat. But it is a defense of looking more broadly. Kalanithi’s work is a beautiful treatise on the macro-level concept of the meaning of life while digging into the important substance of the practice of medicine and patient care today, and the balancing of the competing goals with which practitioners and patients alike are faced.

0 Comments

    Author

    Miranda Yaver is a political scientist, health policy researcher, and comedian in Los Angeles. She received her PhD in Political Science at Columbia University in 2015. She has taught courses on American politics, public policy, law, and quantitative methodology at Washington University in St. Louis, Yale University, Columbia University, and Tufts University.

    Archives

    November 2018
    September 2018
    July 2018
    April 2018
    March 2018
    September 2017
    August 2017
    July 2017
    May 2017
    March 2017
    February 2017
    January 2017
    December 2016
    November 2016
    October 2016
    September 2016
    August 2016
    July 2016
    June 2016
    May 2016
    April 2016
    March 2016

    Categories

    All
    Election
    Health Care
    Misc
    Reproductive Rights
    Supreme Court
    Voting Rights

    RSS Feed